Autonomy and self-determination
György: I think that this is an addiction, just like cigarettes. Or like any other addictions…
Ákos: Yes… sex-addiction
Isi: Actually I’ve already tried to give it up
Ákos: Me too, me too
György: Me too
Ákos: To give up this everyday thing
Isi: I can’t
György: I also said [to myself] what’s good in it?… that I surely wouldn’t do it for a week
Ákos: I swear I tried… [sounds incredulous] I tried… and I swear
Isi: I endured for two weeks, then relapsed
Ákos: I’m like… I must [watch porn] because that’s how I get relaxed, how I discharge daily stress I swear!
György: Yes but yeah really
Young men interviewed by Ferenc Marczali120
This was not a group of young men selected for struggles with their porn use
At its heart, autonomy is both the feeling and the reality of driving oneself and one’s life, rather than being in the passenger seat looking on, a passive recipient of thoughts, feelings, and life experiences. It is the right and condition of self government. Mental autonomy comprises both freedom of thought, as well as the sense of ownership and endorsement of one’s thoughts and feelings. Autonomy extends from there into our decisions, our actions and our opportunities. We enjoy fuller autonomy when we are valued and respected by others and ourselves; when we are supported in developing core capabilities such as self-awareness, critical reflection and imagination; and when we have a range of freedoms and opportunities through which to grow, pursue life goals and achieve wellbeing121.
Mental autonomy is an internationally enshrined human right. Simon McCarthy Jones traces its legal history and its vulnerability to technological development in ‘The autonomous mind: right to freedom of thought in the 21st Century’
In everyday use, autonomy is often understood as individualistic independence, but extensive philosophical and psychological literatures have unpacked its rich connections with our relationships, social nature and compassionate values122. The concept of ‘relational autonomy’123 draws attention to the ways in which people develop their autonomy and act with agency within their web of social influences and connections – in particular highlighting how we own, value and choose our care and commitment towards others.
Autonomy is relevant to all of the other parts of being human that we’ve explored so far. People who place more weight on intrinsic values (such as caring for others and nature) tend to feel more autonomous124 – they have the experience of thinking, feeling and acting on what are felt to be the deepest parts of themselves. And relationships are at their best when both people support the other’s autonomy – indeed love itself cannot exist without it, given love’s essential quality of being ‘fully self-endorsed’125. In contrast, both objectification and manipulation profoundly threaten this core of our personhood, as we will further explore.
Why is autonomy important?
But first, why the emphasis on autonomy? Why is it important? Autonomy’s central role in human flourishing, across cultures, is the main conclusion of hundreds of studies conducted within the framework of Self-Determination Theory126. When we enjoy greater autonomy, we experience greater vitality and life satisfaction. At the same time, it’s value cannot be reduced to its impact on wellbeing127: legal statutes, schools of philosophy and core tenets of our politics all recognise that it is an irreducible ‘good’. Democracies are built on the notion that the people’s will is inherently worthy of respect. And we have an inherent ‘will to will’, to be an author in our own lives, beyond any further benefits this might bring us. Most of us will likely concur with Thomas Scanlon when he writes:
I want to choose the furniture for my own apartment, pick out the pictures for the walls, and even write my own lectures despite the fact that these things might be done better by a decorator, art expert, or talented graduate student. For better or worse, I want these things to be produced by and reflect my own taste, imagination, and powers of discrimination and analysis. I feel the same way, even more strongly, about important decisions affecting my life in larger terms: what career to follow, where to work, how to live.128
What it is to be a person is impossible to conceive of without autonomy. Without this wellspring within us fundamentals to our existence such as self, meaning, creativity, relationships, responsibility, apology and commitment, start to breakdown and lose their substance.
Virginia Woolf noted that ‘a lock on the door means the power to think for oneself’129. We have greater freedom of thought when we have the permission, space, protection and support to contemplate, listen to all parts of ourselves, and find our deepest values. Shoshana Zuboff makes the case for this being a basic right: our right to sanctuary130. This space inside ourselves is our own, it is to be respected and protected and is integral to another right she asserts, the right to the future tense. This is the right to find out who we are, what we want. The right to act on this in the future. The right to be the author of our own life.
Porn users' experience of loss of control
Certain consumers are very heavy users…[their] behaviours are not healthy…. these consumers are particularly important because of the significant financial resources that they pour into the online erotica industry
Jack Morrison, Adult Video News Media Network 131
Pornography’s corrosion of autonomy is most obvious in the experience of individuals who feel addicted to it, and many of its users do. In a large representative sample of Australian adults, 4.4% of men and 1.2% of women reported feeling addicted to pornography132. Younger age is associated with increased risk of porn addiction133; a recent study of Polish University students found that of the 80% of students who said they had seen pornography, 15.5% felt addicted to it134. In the UK it seems that increasing numbers of young people are seeking help for this problem135.
At the same time, the ‘reality’ of porn addiction remains contested. Some voice concern that this narrative frames porn use as a ‘biological danger’ and it does so to maintain ‘traditional moralist fears’ about porn136. Raising different issues, on the basis of their analysis of various media articles and the online response to them, Kris Taylor and Nicola Gavey note how the narrative of addiction works to create categories of ‘appropriate’ and ‘inappropriate’ porn use and, by focussing on ‘disordered individuals’, it diverts attention from the pressing ethical questions about porn itself and its cultural contributors137. Similar concerns have been raised about other addiction narratives (for example related to gambling), and a further worry is that the addiction label can be used to obscure agency and responsibility. It is also not at all clear how exactly to define porn addiction138.
At the heart of addiction is the feeling of having lost control139 When we talk about porn addiction, it’s important that we do so with nuance – sidestepping and challenging unhelpful assumptions like those just noted – whilst not losing sight of these feelings of powerlessness which seem to be what so many are trying to express when they reach for the word ‘addiction’. Interestingly, one of the main findings coming out of the neuroscientific research on pornography is that ‘porn addiction’ on a neurological level resembles other addictions140, as it also does psychologically141. The particular pattern of neural activity in self-described porn addicts compared to controls supports the Incentive Salience Theory (IST) of addiction142, which argues that in addiction ‘wanting’ (anticipated reward) becomes untethered from ‘liking’ (the experienced value of the reward). In other words, people find themselves wanting something that in reality they find unsatisfying, being driven by desires that do not lead to the fulfilment of their goals.
Importantly people struggling with an addiction do not lose all autonomy. In a convincing philosophical exploration, Neil Levy finds that the type of autonomy lost in addiction is the ability to extend one’s agency and oneself across time – Zuboff’s right to a future tense. An addict can ably initiate and execute plans to get hold of the thing she craves but ‘she lacks the capacity effectively to guide her own future behaviour by her will… her preference is temporary and does not reflect her will’143.
Within all of us there are different parts that, consciously or subconsciously, jostle and negotiate with one another. Part of human development is becoming more aware of these different parts of ourselves and clearer on how they best work together and integrate. When we find ourselves dependent on or addicted to something, it is as if one part has jumped into the driving seat, against the will of the others who are in fact better at driving us towards our deepest aspirations. But maybe this is not quite true in the case of porn addiction – instead of an addicted part jumping into a person’s driving seat, it seems more that they have been groomed, lured and pulled into it by the mainstream online porn industry’s tactics and surveillance-driven algorithms. In other words people are manipulated into dependency.
And other addictions such as those to gambling and social media, which can also be fuelled by the practices of those who profit from them.
Manipulation and the porn industry
Manipulation, like coercion or force, is generally recognised as a threat to autonomy. It’s heart and contours (what is must comprise, whether it is always wrong, the critical way it undermines autonomy) are the subject of rich debate. Some scholars argue that it always has a covert element144. Others say that secrecy is not always necessary, but instead insist on another feature such as its disregard of a person’s rationality145. The general conclusion that we can draw is that each of these ‘features’ increases the risk of manipulation and the threat to autonomy (whether or not they are necessary or sufficient): they have each been a focus of attention because there is recognition that when they are present, the situation usually worsens. Interweaving with these discussions is increasing analysis of the extent and impact of the corporate manipulation made possible by technological surveillance, that reaps and then trades in people’s data146.
When we combine all of this scholarship with an analysis of mainstream online porn and the business model behind it (as explored here), we find an industry engaged in extensive manipulation – both of people’s sexuality and other parts of themselves – and this profoundly corrodes people’s ability to be the authors of their own lives and enjoy the freedoms and delights of being ‘fully human’.
To recap and summarise, data is gathered from porn viewers without their informed consent to feed algorithms that shape their porn experience, in turn to shape them towards corporate profit. Drawing on vast amounts of people’s data, these algorithms ‘find’ the human vulnerabilities that can be exploited to hold their attention and in other ways pull them towards spending. Whilst there has been inadequate analysis of the intricacies of porn’s machine processes, the founding president of Facebook, Sean Parker, has indicated that techniques such as intermittent reinforcement were deployed on Facebook, a powerful manipulation which keeps users’ engaged through inconsistently giving them the ‘rewards’ they seek.
When someone visits a porn site and they see content algorithmically chosen for them, there is no explanation of why they are being shown that particular content: what knowledge about them has informed that decision and how, and what that decision is fundamentally trying to achieve. And the barrage of videos and images confronting viewers, creating a fragmentary and disorientating experience, is likely to make it far harder for people to apply clear thinking to their decisions in this zone. An obvious point that bears repeating is that these and the other features of online porn reviewed here work in the interests of the corporation, not the user. Going further, and drawing on everything that we have explored so far, they work against the person’s interests. As we’ve explored, we flourish, both individually and collectively, when we respect our own and others’ full personhood, when we love both ourselves and one another, and when we have the freedom and support to author ourselves, our lives and our relationships in alignment with our deepest values.
In short, the mainstream online porn industry — through both covert and overt means — seeks to shape people’s sexuality towards its own interests, which are in opposition to the interests of its users (and in opposition to the interests of others upon whom it impacts). It would seem to exploit psychological vulnerabilities, is e xtensive in its scope, and is disinterested in viewers’ rationality, values, or wellbeing. As such it is both an archetypal and thoroughly modern manipulator. We suggest that fundamentally this manipulation undermines viewers’ autonomy by making it harder for them to think and act with self-awareness and critical reflection, by stimulating sexual scripts that conflict with other parts of themselves, and by increasing the power of superficial, temporal preferences relative to their deeper aspirations, values and beliefs.
In all of this people’s Right to Freedom of Thought is violated, as this of course includes the right not to have one’s thoughts manipulated147. The boundaries of their inner mental sanctuary are broken. Viewers are treated as organisms to be herded, prodded and shaped towards corporate profit. Like those they view on screen, users are themselves objectified, their sexuality – this core and intimate part of ourselves – seen as ‘fair game’ in a game that they’re not playing, a game that they are at best only vaguely aware of.
It’s no wonder then that so many find themselves feeling addicted to porn, in conflict between using it and not wanting to, finding their ability to extend their agency over time, to be the person they want to be, deeply compromised. But of course not everyone feels this way. A set of studies find that porn users are more likely to see themselves as addicted when they experience moral incongruence: when they are aware of a conflict between their porn use and their moral values148. At the opposite end of the spectrum are those with entrenched beliefs that complement their porn use (for example, attitudes that are sexist, or support inequality or aggression). Between both poles are likely many who hold a conflicting mix of values and views, and who are unused to critical ethical reflection on the content of porn and their use of it149. During their porn use, conflicting parts of themselves are suppressed or ignored. Unlike the first group, these individuals feel as if they have more control over their porn use, because they are less likely to have tried to stop and their decision to use it feels more ‘their own’.
But these users are still subject to the same strategies and manipulations. Their autonomy is still compromised even without this being a felt experience. Pornography has curtailed their freedoms, for example, to author a sexuality rooted in respect, intimacy and connection150. In an analysis of how AI systems can support (or detract from) human autonomy, Rafael Calvo and colleagues draw attention to six spheres of technology experience (adoption, interface, tasks, behaviour, life and society) and show how a particular platform, app or device may be autonomy-supportive in one sphere but detract from it in others. The domains of society and life are the most important, the latter being ‘the extent to which a technology influences the fulfilment of psychological needs, such as autonomy, within life overall, this potentially affecting the extent to which one is thriving’151. Drawing on recent research on the impact of fitness wearables on motivation152 they demonstrate the contradictory ways a particular technology can influence our autonomy: whilst a tracker can feel autonomy-supportive at the adoption, interface, task and behaviour levels (for example a person chooses to use one without being manipulated to and find it motivates them to exercise), over time these devices increase guilt and pressure, and reduce overall ‘psychological need satisfaction’. So too we assert with pornography: users can feel completely in control when viewing it, whilst all the while it is cutting away their more profound life freedoms and controls.
In an insightful analysis of social media’s manipulative power, Sylvie Delacroix argues that its hidden influence combined with its precise and comprehensive scope combine to create a particularly potent manipulative influence and threat to our autonomy. When people are gradually drawn along a path by a multitude of hidden influences, they may lose a capacity essential to autonomy: the ability to imagine oneself as a different person. For example, when someone has gone on an online journey into extremism, pushed and pulled a thousand times, they may arrive at a place where this viewpoint feels authentically their own and of their choosing, but what is missing here is their ability to see and relate to their ‘shadow self’ – who they were or could have been. In these circumstances there is not ‘enough left of us that is free of manipulatory influence to anchor some after-the-fact endorsement or alienation test’153.
We suggest that this is exactly what is happening to many porn users. Returning to Figure 1, once people have entered the blue and purple zones of manipulated sexuality, they may forget what their ‘green’ sexuality looked and felt like, and they feel like they could never return to it, it is no longer ‘them’. And when porn has been viewed from a young age, a person’s sexuality without porn may feel inconceivable. What a ‘yellow’ sexuality could look and feel like, i.e. where one’s sexuality would have ended up without manipulative influence, is likely even harder to fathom. The invisible tragedy here is that people are losing what they never knew they could have, having something taken away from them before it was even given, owned, and enjoyed.
Porn and the autonomy of women and girls
So far our discussion has focussed on how porn undermines the autonomy of its users. However, they are not the only group whose autonomy it affects. Our analysis as a whole points to varied ways in which the autonomy of women and girls is particularly harmed by porn, given how it routinely narrates them as objects (often of humiliation and denigration), as well as passive, and without desire beyond pleasuring men. So, for example, when women and girls experience porn-inspired objectification (whether from themselves or others), their self-development and self-acceptance is endangered. When they are subjected to porn-inspired sexual harassment and abuse, not only are their rights violated, their freedoms to learn, socialise and play are cut back. When they experience porn-inspired sex, they often miss out on sexual flow, immersion and fulfilment. And when their relationships sour or end as a result of porn, they lose love and connection. All of this returns us to the sense of quiet tragedy unfolding around us.
-
Marczali, F. (2015). Problems with the feminist pro-porn discourse and its fantasy about the male subject of pornography. Doctoral dissertation: Central European University.
-
Mackenzie, C. (2014). Three dimensions of autonomy: A relational analysis. In Autonomy, oppression and gender (pp. 15-41). Oxford University Press.
-
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2017c). Self-determination theory: Basic psychological needs in motivation, development, and wellness. Guilford Publications.
Veltman, A., & Piper, M. (Eds.). (2014). Introduction in A. Veltman & M. Piper (Eds.) Autonomy, oppression, and gender. Oxford University Press.
-
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2017). Self-determination theory: Basic psychological needs in motivation, development, and wellness. Guilford Publications.
Kasser, T. (2016). Materialistic Values and Goals, Annual Review of Psychology
-
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2017b). Relationships Motivation Theory: The self in close relationships. Chapter 12 in Self-determination theory: Basic psychological needs in motivation, development, and wellness. Guilford Publications. p. 294
-
Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2017). Self-determination theory: Basic psychological needs in motivation, development, and wellness. Guilford Publications.
-
Sen, 2010
-
Scanlon, T. (1986) The Significance of Choice, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, 149-180.
-
Woolf, V. (2001). A Room of One’s Own. Ontario, ON: Broadview Press, p125
-
Zuboff, S. (2019) The Age of Surveillance Capitalism: The Fight for a Human Future at the New Frontier of Power. Profile.
-
Morrison, J (2004) ‘The distracted porn consumer: you never knew your online customers so well. Adult Video News Media Network. Accessed September 2020
-
Rissel, C., Richters, J., de Visser, R.O., McKee, A., Yeung, A., Caruana, T. (2017) A Profile of Pornography Users in Australia: Findings from the Second Australian Study of Health and Relationships. Journal of Sex Research 54, 227–240.
-
de Alarcón, R., de la Iglesia, J. I., Casado, N. M., & Montejo, A. L. (2019). Online porn addiction: What we know and what we don’t—A systematic review. Journal of clinical medicine, 8(1), 91.
-
Dwulit, A. D., & Rzymski, P. (2019). Prevalence, patterns and self-perceived effects of pornography consumption in Polish university students: a cross-sectional study. International journal of environmental research and public health, 16(10), 1861.
-
Evans, M. (2020). Porn effects: ‘My expectations of sex and body image were warped’. BBC News website. Accessed June 2021
-
Clarkson, J., & Kopaczewski, S. (2013). Pornography addiction and the medicalization of free speech. Journal of Communication Inquiry, 37(2), 128-148.
-
Taylor, K., & Gavey, N. (2020). Pornography addiction and the perimeters of acceptable pornography viewing. Sexualities, 23(5-6), 876-897.
-
Duffy, A., Dawson, D. L., & Das Nair, R. (2016). Pornography addiction in adults: A systematic review of definitions and reported impact. The Journal of Sexual Medicine, 13(5), 760-777.
-
For example, see the criteria for addictive disorders in the DSM-V (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders) or ICD-11 (International Classification of Diseases).
Also see:
Orford, J. (2013). Power, powerlessness and addiction. Cambridge University Press
Levy, N. (2006). Autonomy and addiction. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 36(3), 427-447.
de Alarcón, R., de la Iglesia, J. I., Casado, N. M., & Montejo, A. L. (2019). Online porn addiction: What we know and what we don’t—A systematic review. Journal of clinical medicine, 8(1), 91.
-
Gola, M., Wordecha, M., Sescousse, G., Lew-Starowicz, M., Kossowski, B., Wypych, M., ... & Marchewka, A. (2017). Can pornography be addictive? An fMRI study of men seeking treatment for problematic pornography use. Neuropsychopharmacology, 42(10), 2021-2031.
Kowalewska, E., Grubbs, J. B., Potenza, M. N., Gola, M., Draps, M., & Kraus, S. W. (2018). Neurocognitive mechanisms in compulsive sexual behavior disorder. Current Sexual Health Reports, 10(4), 255-264.
-
de Alarcón, R., de la Iglesia, J. I., Casado, N. M., & Montejo, A. L. (2019). Online porn addiction: What we know and what we don’t—A systematic review. Journal of clinical medicine, 8(1), 91.
-
Robinson, T. E., & Berridge, K. C. (1993). The neural basis of drug craving: an incentive-sensitization theory of addiction. Brain research reviews, 18(3), 247-291.
-
Levy, N. (2006). Autonomy and addiction. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 36(3), 427-447.
-
Susser, D., Roessler, B., & Nissenbaum, H. (2019). Technology, autonomy, and manipulation. Internet Policy Review, 8(2).
-
Klenk, M., & Hancock, J. (2019). Autonomy and Online Manipulation. Internet Policy Review.
Klenk, M. (2020). Digital well-being and manipulation online. In Ethics of Digital Well-Being (pp. 81-100). Springer, Cham.
-
For example:
Zuboff, S. (2019) The Age of Surveillance Capitalism: The Fight for a Human Future at the New Frontier of Power. Profile.
Büchi, M., Fosch-Villaronga, E., Lutz, C., Tamò-Larrieux, A., Velidi, S., & Viljoen, S. (2020). The chilling effects of algorithmic profiling: Mapping the issues. Computer Law & Security Review, 36, 105367.
McCarthy-Jones, S. (2019). The autonomous mind: The right to freedom of thought in the twenty-first century. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence, 2, 19, 1-17
-
McCarthy-Jones, S. (2019). The autonomous mind: The right to freedom of thought in the twenty-first century. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence, 2, 19, 1-17
-
Lewczuk, K., Nowakowska, I., Lewandowska, K., Potenza, M. N., & Gola, M. (2021). Frequency of use, moral incongruence and religiosity and their relationships with self‐perceived addiction to pornography, internet use, social networking and online gaming. Addiction, 116(4), 889-899.
Grubbs, J. B., & Perry, S. L. (2019). Moral incongruence and pornography use: A critical review and integration. The Journal of Sex Research, 56(1), 29-37.
-
Antevska, A., & Gavey, N. (2015). “Out of Sight and Out of Mind” Detachment and Men’s Consumption of Male Sexual Dominance and Female Submission in Pornography. Men and Masculinities, 18(5), 605-629.
-
Dines, G. (2017). Growing up with porn: The developmental and societal impact of pornography on children. Dignity: A Journal on Sexual Exploitation and Violence, 2(3), Article 3 (9 pages).
-
Calvo, R. A., Peters, D., Vold, K., & Ryan, R. M. (2020). Supporting human autonomy in AI systems: A framework for ethical enquiry. In Ethics of Digital Well-Being (pp. 31-54). Springer, Cham.
-
Kerner, C., & Goodyear, V. A. (2017). The motivational impact of wearable healthy lifestyle technologies: a self-determination perspective on Fitbits with adolescents. American Journal of Health Education. 48,5, 287-297 https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/pdf/10.1080/19325037.2017.1343161
-
Delacroix, S. (2020). Social Media Manipulation, Autonomy and Capabilities. Autonomy and Capabilities (October 13, 2020).